Kind: Difference between revisions

From The Toaq Wiki
mNo edit summary
(Updated binding note to include the proposal where baq does bind a variable)
Line 12: Line 12:


== Semantics ==
== Semantics ==
{{t|baq rảı}} does not introduce a scope<ref>https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/311223912044167168/652268988931506236</ref>, and does not bind a variable {{t|ráı}}. Instead it behaves like a constant like '''jí''' or '''súq'''.
When we fill an argument place with a {{t|baq}}-term, the logical meaning of the resulting claim depends on the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Predicate_(grammar)#Carlson_classes '''Carlson class'''] of the predicate with regards to that argument place.
When we fill an argument place with a {{t|baq}}-term, the logical meaning of the resulting claim depends on the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Predicate_(grammar)#Carlson_classes '''Carlson class'''] of the predicate with regards to that argument place.


Line 21: Line 19:


(These classes originated in linguistics to describe the apparent variety in meanings an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" can take on in different sentences. So in a sense, an easy way to think about '''baq kảtō''' is to treat it the way you'd treat an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" in English.)
(These classes originated in linguistics to describe the apparent variety in meanings an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" can take on in different sentences. So in a sense, an easy way to think about '''baq kảtō''' is to treat it the way you'd treat an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" in English.)
== Binding ==
Hoemai said in 2019 that {{t|baq pỏq}} does not introduce a scope<ref>https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/311223912044167168/652268988931506236</ref>, and does not bind a variable {{t|pỏq}}. Instead it behaves like a constant like '''jí''' or '''súq'''. It has also been proposed that {{t|baq pỏq}} could bind {{t|pỏq}} after all, so that a sentence like {{t|Chỏ baq shỉ pỏq shí pỏq}} could mean "People like themselves". The other possible sentence, "people like people", could still be rendered as {{t|Chỏ baq shỉ pỏq baq shỉ pỏq}}.


== The typical… ==
== The typical… ==

Revision as of 11:42, 23 September 2021

Toaq has a quantifier, baq, which is used to talk about kinds of things, rather than some or all instances of them.

For example, baq tủzȳ means "soup" (or "soup-kind", or "soup in general") rather than sa tủzȳ "some soup" or tu tủzȳ "all soup".

Why have kinds?

The need for a way to make claims about kinds is apparent from examples like the following:

  • "Dinosaurs are extinct" can not be expressed as [∀d: Dinosaur(d)] Extinct(d). Individual dinosaurs are not extinct, only dead. Dinosaurs, as a kind, are extinct.
  • "Cats are widespread" can not be expressed as [∃c: Cat(c)] Widespread(c). Individual cats cannot be widespread. Not even "many cats are widespread".
  • Even "I'll make some soup" can not be expressed as [∃s: Soup(s)] WillMake(i, s). You aren't saying of some certain instance S of soup that you'll make it. Instead, the Toaq way of looking at this meaning of "make" is that we are "manifesting a kind"[1]. So we say bảı jí baq tủzȳ, and only the result of our efforts (if we succeed) is sa tủzȳ.

So, a language appears to need a way to make claims about kinds without quantifying over their individuals. One solution is to define predicates like "___ makes something satisfying property ___" and "The kind satisfying property ___ is extinct", and then fill them with lî tủzȳ. (This is the approach taken by pre-kind Toaq lıbāı, or Lojban jaukpa.) But then we are really just tucking away the grammatical concept of kinds in those English definitions. Moreover, it is unnaturally indirect for "X makes Y" to be a c 1 word when it very much feels like we are talking about things and not properties.

Semantics

When we fill an argument place with a baq-term, the logical meaning of the resulting claim depends on the Carlson class of the predicate with regards to that argument place.

  1. Kind-level predicates, such as "___ are extinct" and "___ are widespread", just make a direct claim about the kind, rather than any individuals of it. They are usually nonsensical when filled with sa or tu terms.
  2. Individual-level predicates are true of their argument "no matter when": descriptions not tied to a timeline, like "___ is/are intelligent". A baq argument to such a predicate is interpreted as a general (but maybe not tu-universal?) claim over the individuals of the kind: "cats are intelligent", i.e. (pretty much?) any cat is intelligent.
  3. Stage-level predicates are true only of their argument in their current temporal stage. A baq argument to such a predicate is reduced to its sa equivalent: "cats are playing" means "some cats are playing".

(These classes originated in linguistics to describe the apparent variety in meanings an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" can take on in different sentences. So in a sense, an easy way to think about baq kảtō is to treat it the way you'd treat an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" in English.)

Binding

Hoemai said in 2019 that baq pỏq does not introduce a scope[2], and does not bind a variable pỏq. Instead it behaves like a constant like or súq. It has also been proposed that baq pỏq could bind pỏq after all, so that a sentence like Chỏ baq shỉ pỏq shí pỏq could mean "People like themselves". The other possible sentence, "people like people", could still be rendered as Chỏ baq shỉ pỏq baq shỉ pỏq.

The typical…

baq does not mean "the typical X" (and never has).[3] Typicality is orthogonal to baq:[4] you can call individual three-leaf clovers "typical", or say that baq clover rarely has four leaves.

External links