734
edits
(Updated binding note to include the proposal where baq does bind a variable) |
(update math, copy over quoted material, et cætera) |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
Toaq has a | Toaq has a quantieier, {{t|baq}}, which is used to talk about '''kinds''' of things, rather than some or all instances of them. | ||
For example, {{t|baq | For example, {{t|baq tủzy}} means "soup" (or "soup-kind", or "soup in general") rather than {{t|sa tủzy}} "some soup" or {{t|tu tủzy}} "all soup". | ||
== Why have kinds? == | == Why have kinds? == | ||
The need for a way to make claims about kinds is apparent from examples like the following: | The need for a way to make claims about kinds is apparent from examples like the following: | ||
* "Dinosaurs are extinct" can not be expressed as < | * "Dinosaurs are extinct" can not be expressed as <math>\left[\forall D\colon \text{Dinosaur}(D)\right] \text{Extinct}(D)</math>. Individual dinosaurs are not extinct, only dead. Dinosaurs, as a kind, are extinct. | ||
* "Cats are widespread" can not be expressed as < | * "Cats are widespread" can not be expressed as <math>\left[\exists C\colon \text{Cat}(C)\right] \text{Widespread}(C)</math>. Individual cats cannot be widespread. Not even "many cats are widespread". | ||
* Even "I'll make some soup" can not be expressed as < | * Even "I'll make some soup" can not be expressed as <math>\left[\exists S\colon \text{Soup}(S)\right] \text{WillMake}(\text{I}, S)</math>. You aren't saying of some certain instance ''S'' of soup that you'll make it. Instead, the Toaq way of looking at this meaning of "make" is that we are "manifesting a kind"<ref name=manifesting-a-kind />. So we say {{t|bảı jí baq tủzy}}, and only the result of our efforts (if we succeed) is {{t|sa tủzy}}. | ||
So, a language appears to need a way to make claims about kinds without quantifying over their individuals. One solution is to define predicates like " | So, a language appears to need a way to make claims about kinds without quantifying over their individuals. One solution is to define predicates like "{{x}} makes something satisfying property {{x}}" and "The kind satisfying property {{x}} is extinct", and then fill them with {{t|tûzy ja}}. (This is the approach taken by pre-kind Toaq {{t|lıbaı}}, or Lojban <code>jaukpa</code>.) But then we are really just tucking away the grammatical concept of kinds in those English definitions. Moreover, it is unnaturally indirect for "X makes Y" to be a <code>c 1</code> word when it very much feels like we are talking about ''things'' and not properties. | ||
== Semantics == | == Semantics == | ||
When we fill an argument place with a {{t|baq}}-term, the logical meaning of the resulting claim depends on the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Predicate_(grammar)#Carlson_classes '''Carlson class'''] of the predicate with regards to that argument place. | When we fill an argument place with a {{t|baq}}-term, the logical meaning of the resulting claim depends on the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Predicate_(grammar)#Carlson_classes '''Carlson class'''] of the predicate with regards to that argument place. | ||
# '''Kind-level''' predicates, such as " | # '''Kind-level''' predicates, such as "{{x}} are extinct" and "{{x}} are widespread", just make a direct claim ''about'' the kind, rather than any individuals of it. They are usually nonsensical when filled with {{t|sa}} or {{t|tu}} terms. | ||
# '''Individual-level''' predicates are true of their argument "no matter when": descriptions not tied to a timeline, like " | # '''Individual-level''' predicates are true of their argument "no matter when": descriptions not tied to a timeline, like "{{x}} is/are intelligent". A {{t|baq}} argument to such a predicate is interpreted as a general (but maybe not {{t|tu}}-universal?) claim over the individuals of the kind: "cats are intelligent", i.e. (pretty much?) any cat is intelligent. | ||
# '''Stage-level''' predicates are true only of their argument in their current temporal stage. A {{t|baq}} argument to such a predicate is reduced to its {{t|sa}} equivalent: "cats are playing" means "some cats are playing". | # '''Stage-level''' predicates are true only of their argument in their current temporal stage. A {{t|baq}} argument to such a predicate is reduced to its {{t|sa}} equivalent: "cats are playing" means "some cats are playing". | ||
(These classes originated in linguistics to describe the apparent variety in meanings an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" can take on in different sentences. So in a sense, an easy way to think about | (These classes originated in linguistics to describe the apparent variety in meanings an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" can take on in different sentences. So in a sense, an easy way to think about {{t|baq kảto}} is to treat it the way you'd treat an indefinite noun phrase like "cats" in English.) | ||
== Binding == | == Binding == | ||
Hoemai said in 2019 that {{t|baq pỏq}} does not introduce a scope<ref | Hoemai said in 2019 that {{t|baq pỏq}} does not introduce a scope<ref name=no-scope />, and does not bind a variable {{t|pỏq}}. Instead it behaves like a constant like {{t|jí}} or {{t|súq}}. It has also been proposed that {{t|baq pỏq}} could bind {{t|pỏq}} after all, so that a sentence like {{t|Chỏ baq shỉ pỏq shí pỏq}} could mean "People like themselves". The other possible sentence, "people like people", could still be rendered as {{t|Chỏ baq shỉ pỏq baq shỉ pỏq}}. | ||
== The typical… == | == The typical… == | ||
{{t|baq}} does not mean "the typical X" (and never has).<ref name="not-typical" /> Typicality is orthogonal to {{t|baq}}:<ref name="orthogonal" /> you can call individual three-leaf clovers "typical", or say that {{t|baq}} clover rarely has four leaves. | |||
== External links == | == External links == | ||
<ul> | |||
<li>[https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/311223912044167168/663107948628934706 Hoemaı's "gist" about baq and Carlson classes] on Discord {{Transcript|[[Hoemaı]]:<poem> | |||
So, gist: | |||
There are three types of predicates when it comes to {{t|baq}} predication. | |||
1) Kind predicates | |||
2) stage level predicates | |||
3) individual level predicates | |||
These are properties of predicates, or more exactly, of their argument places. | |||
Depending on the place type, different things happen with {{t|baq}}. | |||
Kind predicates make claims about kinds themselves. These cannot be paraphrased using sa. Examples: dinosaurs are extinct != there exist some dinosaurs that are extinct; cats are widespread != there are some cats that are widespread; looking for gold != there is some gold such that I’m looking for it | |||
Using {{t|baq}} with stage level predicates can be reduced to sa. These are predicates that a otherwise used with non-{{t|baq}} arguments. ({{t|baq}}) cats are in my garden = there are some cats in my garden | |||
Individual level predicates are also predicates that basically use non-{{t|baq}} arguments. When using {{t|baq}} in those places, it can't be paraphrased using sa. dogs are smart != there are some dogs that are smart | |||
Summary: No matter which kind of predicate you're dealing with, every non-{{t|baq}} place can also be filled by a {{t|baq}} argument, but not every {{t|baq}} place can be filled by non-{{t|baq}} arguments. | |||
(There isn't that much left to spoil, other than the real reason why {{t|baq}} is a quantifier/determiner) | |||
</poem>}}</li> | |||
</ul> | |||
<references> | |||
<ref name="manifesting-a-kind"> | |||
https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/311223912044167168/663073088883392518 | |||
{{Transcript|[[Hoemaı]]:<poem> | |||
As for {{t|baı}}, there are two meanings of "make/build" | |||
The first one, which is the one used in the TwE example above, is something like "to manifest a kind". | |||
The other, which is distinct from the first, is the one that you use to say "I made this table". | |||
You can use the first to say the second one, but only indirectly: "This table is the result of me manifesting table kind" | |||
</poem>}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name="no-scope"> | |||
https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/311223912044167168/652268988931506236 | |||
{{Transcript| | |||
<blockquote>[[Hoaqgıo]]: I guess [{{t|baq}}] doesn't create scope</blockquote> | |||
[[Hoemaı]]: No, it's a reference to a kind. | |||
}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name="not-typical"> | |||
https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/334810940392341514/711970941240082502 | |||
{{Transcript|[[Hoemaı]]: {{t|baq}} does not mean "typical" (and never has).}} | |||
</ref> | |||
<ref name="orthogonal"> | |||
https://discord.com/channels/311223912044167168/361588038586990592/684027791146090526 | |||
{{Transcript|[[Hoemaı]]:<poem> | |||
''[image of a three-leaf clover beside a four-leaf clover]'' | |||
"The thing on the left is a typical clover." | |||
"({{t|baq}}) Typical clovers have three leaves." | |||
"({{t|baq}}) clovers are plants." | |||
Typicality is orthogonal to baq. | |||
(typicality is indirectly related because it comes into play when we try to judge whether certain generic claims are true or not, but baq itself does not mean "the typical") | |||
</poem>}} | |||
</ref> | |||
</references> |